Sunday, November 10, 2024

3658. Arundhati Roy on Israel/U.S. Genocidal War in Gaza/Palestine

 By Arundhati Roy, October 2024 



Arundhati Roy, the internationally celebrated author and human rights activist's speech upon receiving the PEN Foundation’s annual Pinter Prize in October 2024, Roy announced that she’d be donating her prize money to the Palestinian Children’s Relief Fund.

Named for the late British playwright Harold Pinter, the PEN Pinter Prize and the Pinter International Writer of Courage awards have been distributed annually since 2009.

Transcription into Farsi is by Abdi Kalantari. 


Saturday, November 9, 2024

3657. Why Trump Again: A Note on the 2024 U.S. Elections

By Kamran Nayeri, November 8, 2024



Editor's Note: The Farsi edition of this short commentary was published in the socialist website Critique of Political Economy (نقد اقتصاد سیاسی). The free English translation is by the author. 

*.    *.     *

Contrary to the expectations of Democratic Party supporters, the victory of Trump and the Republican Party in November 2024 elections was complete.  Peter B. Baker, who wrote a book about Trump, wrote in the New York Times on November 6: "The assumption that Mr. Trump  is a fleeting  phenomenon and will soon be consigned to the dustbin of history on Tuesday night as the red wave swept  through the country, including in those states that did not yet  favor  either presidential candidate. It was wrong." Three reporters from Reid Epstein, Lisa Lerer and Nicholas Nehamas, wrote on Nov. 7 that 

“What was indisputable was how badly Democrats did. They lost the White House, surrendered control of the Senate and appeared headed to defeat in the House. They performed worse than four years ago in cities and suburbs, rural towns and college towns. An early New York Times analysis of the results found the vast majority of the nation’s more than 3,100 counties swinging rightward since President Biden won in 2020.”

They quote Bernie Sanders that the Democratic Party “which increasingly has become a party of identity politics, rather than understanding that the vast majority of people in this country are working class. This trend of workers leaving the Democratic Party started with whites, and it has accelerated to Latinos and Blacks.”

However, it would be a mistake to reduce the reasons for the Democrats' defeat to economic issues. There is a tendency to distrust both parties, especially the Democrats. In 2020, Trump received 74,223,975 votes. But in this election, 71,353,269 people voted for him, which is 2,870,708 less. In 2020, Biden received 81,283,501 votes, but Harris in 2024 has 66,405,656 votes, which is 14,867,845 fewer votes. Both parties had fewer votes in this election, but Democrats have lost more support. 

One reason for this is that the Democratic Party has surpassed the Republicans in its imperialist warmongering policies. Among the "achievements" of the Biden administration are his push to expand NATO and fan the flames of war in Ukraine and unconditional support for Israel's genocidal war in Gaza and its extension the West Bank, Lebanon, and now Iran. Democrats berate Trump and his Republican supporters as "isolationists" because they have less appetiate for U.S. military interventions around the world. American Arabs and Muslims, who usually voted for Democrats, have voted for Trump in their majority. The reason for this is Biden's support for Zionism and Israel's war in Gaza. 

Kamala Harris called Trump a fascist in her election campaign.  Liberals and some leftist currents also call the Trump phenomenon as fascism. They cite his anti-immigrant politics, especially against Latinos and Muslims, his misogyny, and anti-democratic and authoritarian actions and ideas. During his presidency small fascist armed groups calling themselves militias were  active and they were involved in the riots of January 6, 2021. 

However, this situation is fundamentally different from what existed in Germany, Italy and Spain in the 1920s and 1930s analyzed by socialists as fascism. Fascism at that time was a bourgeois in response to the vast and deep crisis of capitalism in Europe when there was also mass trade unions and powerful social-democratic and Communist parties, and as the Soviet Union was rapidly industrializing and arming itself. At that time, the capitalist classes found themselves in serious and immediate danger of the socialist revolution. Fascism was created to crush the workers' and socialist movements by large organized and armed anti-labor and anti-communist fascist groups. In the United States today, there are no mass trade unions, powerful socialist and communist parties, or any "communist" states that threaten capitalism. On the contrary, capitalism dominate the whole world facing no serious opposition. 

The Relative Decline of American Imperialism and Capitalist Political Crisis

The Industrial Revolution of England (1830-1870) turned that country into the superpower dominating the world economy. However, Germany and the United States went through their industrial revolution at the end of the 19th century and overtook England economically with the creation of modern industries and new products by 1913. The First and Second World Wars were fought to create a new order between the imperialist powers.  At the end of World War II, the United States became the global capitalist superpower. Some have called this period the "American Century." 

However, since 2000, the top position of the United States has been threatened by the industrialization of China, which has a population of 1.5 billion. Currently, China produces 20% of the world's industrial products, mainly for export,  while the share of the United States,  which was 40% in 1960, has fallen to 18%.  China  excels in modern infrastructure, new industries, and new products, and is highly competitive in the global market. Meanwhile, China's domestic market  is expanding rapidly with a middle class estimated to be about 300 million. In contrast, the United States has a total population  of 330 million people, and  its middle class  is shrinking. China's economy is still growing by the engine of industrial development, but the U.S. economy is largely dependent on the service sector, which makes for slower  productivity and economic growth. 

The  relative economic decline of the United States has threatened its military position. Although after the collapse of the Soviet Union in 1991, it seemed that the United States had become the  hegemonic power in a unipolar world, it soon became a multipolar world. and now the dominance of the United States in challenged in the Pacific, the Middle East, Africa, and even Latin America, which Washington has called its “backyard” since the time of Monroe Docterine of 1823.

The process  of deindustrialization in the United States due to globalization has  weakened some industries and regions and led to the decline  of the U.S. middle class—especially the white working-class aristocracy—which has ignited the flames of reactionary nativism, white nationalism, and retrogressive capitalist economic views. The Trump phenomenon and its slogan "Make America Great Again” have emerged in this context. 

The neoliberal policies that had been embraced by both parties since the Reagan presidency have long exhausted their use to uplift the U.S. economy. Democratic Party politicians have opted for Keynesian fiscal and monetary policies to modernize the infrastructure and develop new  industries and new products, along with social policies to motivate the working people and strengthen the middle  class to increase productivity growth and expand  the domestic and global market of the United States. 

The intensification of the conflict over these strategies between the Democratic and Republican parties are the result of the relative decline of U.S. imperialism. 

The 2024 presidential and congressional elections should be examined in this context 

The Need for an Independent Ecocentric-Based Socialist Policy

Neither of the two parties of US imperialism and their presidential candidates paid any attention to the urgent needs of the working people in this country and globally. Today, humanity and life on the planet face four existential threats: catastrophic climate change, the Sixth Extinction, recurrent pandemics, and nuclear holocaust. Two bloody wars, one in Ukraine between Western imperialism and Russian imperialism, and the other, an expanding genocidal war by the colonial-settler state of Israel in Gaza, now expanded to the West bank, Lebanon and even to a war with Iran which will require direct U.S. military intervention in the Middle East. 

The root cause of all these crises is the anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization which both parties uphold and defend. Instead, both parties supports the $1.7 trillion program for the modernization of the U.S. nuclear arsenal and currently the U.S. military preparation for war with China. 

Just as the two world wars of the twentieth century were aimed at creating a new order between the imperialist powers, the economic rivalry between China and the United States could quickly escalate into a war between the two nuclear powers. In the war in Ukraine, there were several overt threats of use of nuclear weapons by Putin. According to press reports, Biden explored the possibility of using nuclear weapons against Russia last April. 

The future of humanity and life on the Earth depend on the development of independent power mass organizations the working people to transcend anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization in the direction of Ecocentric Socialist society worldwide, especially in the United States.  

Monday, November 4, 2024

3656. Peter Singer: An Interview

By David Marchese, The New York Times, November 2, 2024

Peter Singer

I believe that most of us, in our own humble ways, try to make the world better. Maybe that means giving what we can to charity or helping out in our community. Maybe it means eating less meat or driving less often. It’s enough for each of us to do our own little part.

Not so, says Peter Singer. Singer, who is 78 and recently retired from a long teaching career at Princeton, is perhaps the world’s most influential living philosopher. His unstinting work grows out of utilitarianism, which is the view that we should do as much as possible to bring about the greatest circumstance for every individual being — and “being” does not necessarily mean “human.” His 1975 book, “Animal Liberation,” a broadside against factory farming and a defense of animal rights, helped galvanize a movement toward vegan and vegetarian eating. (Singer’s new book, “Consider the Turkey,” is a polemic against the enormous animal suffering that goes into the traditional Thanksgiving turkey feast.) And his writing on what the relatively affluent owe to the poor — short version: a lot more — was an important building block for the data-driven philanthropic movement known as effective altruism, which became popular with high-profile Silicon Valley figures including the disgraced cryptocurrency magnate Sam Bankman-Fried. (As well as plenty of regular people looking to do more good, more efficiently.)


But Singer is as controversial as he is influential. Not so much for his attempts to disrupt complacent common-sense ethical beliefs — that, for example, we’re justified in prioritizing the welfare of those close to us over that of strangers far away — but more for his arguments in support of things like allowing parents to pursue euthanasia for severely disabled infants. It’s those ideas that have led Singer to being called dangerous, a eugenicist and worse. None of which seems to matter much to Singer, who, as always, is determined to follow his ethical ideas wherever they may lead.


I promise I don’t mean this in a facetious way: Why did you write “Consider the Turkey”? It’s a small book. There aren’t really new arguments in it. Could that time have been better spent doing something else? This is an important issue. We’re talking about over 200 million turkeys who are reared in a way that comes close to being described as torture. It hurts them to stand up because their immature leg bones don’t bear the immense weight that they’ve been bred to put on in a short time. They suffer at slaughter and, as I describe in the book, if they get bird flu, the entire shed is killed by heatstroke quite commonly. It’s not the only method used in the United States, but it’s used on millions of birds. The ventilation is stopped in the shed, heaters are brought in, and they are deliberately heated to death over a period of hours. That’s something that Americans don’t know, and it’s important they should know, because it should stop. I think that’s definitely worth the time it took to write this book.


It feels hard to deny the unacceptable level of suffering that goes into our Thanksgiving turkey dinners. But millions of people are still going to have them. Do you ever feel as if you’re banging your head against the wall with this stuff? No. I feel like I’m banging my head against something which is pretty hard but not completely unyielding. In some parts of the world, we’ve made progress in the laws and regulations concerning animals. On the whole, yes, things are still bad, but it’s possible to make progress, and we have to keep bringing these facts in front of the public and getting them to think about what they’re eating. The Thanksgiving meal seems like a good place to start.


There’s a journalistic trope of how to talk to your ideologically opposed relative at Thanksgiving. So, if someone reads your book and thinks, Well, now I have something to say about eating this turkey at Thanksgiving, what guidance can you give them about how to have that conversation? Be civil and reasonable. Say, “Have a look at some of these facts” and “Do you really want to be complicit in these practices?” If somebody doesn’t accept the argument or insists this is irrelevant or they’re not going to listen, at some point, you might say, “If you want me at your Thanksgiving, I don’t want to be there with a big bird sitting on the table who has suffered in the ways the standard American Thanksgiving turkey has suffered.”


You would suggest drawing that hard line? Yes. At some point you want to say — and isn’t that true of important moral issues? — “Sorry, I just can’t go along with that.” 

The philosopher Peter Singer, in the black shirt, protesting outside an Australian pig farm in 1992.Credit...Robert Pearce/Fairfax Media, via Getty Images

An offshoot of effective altruism is longtermism. Which is basically the idea that we have as much ethical responsibility to address threats to humanity far off in the future as we do threats in the present. I’m curious what you make of that. I accept the idea that when suffering occurs is not affected by time. If I could be certain that something I did now would do more to reduce suffering in 100 or even 1,000 years than anything I could do to relieve suffering in the present, then sure, I would think that would be the right thing to do. But we don’t have that certainty about the future. That’s a big barrier to making it a real priority to think about the future as more important than the present. The other question that needs to be raised is a deep philosophical question about the risk of extinction of our species. That’s what a lot of longtermists are focused on. They’re saying: “If our species gets through the next century or two, then it’s likely that humans will be around not just for thousands but for millions of years, because by then we’ll be able to colonize other planets. If we become extinct, none of that will happen, so we must give a very high priority to reducing the risk of extinction of our species.” And that raises the question of, is it as bad that beings do not come into existence and therefore do not have happy lives as it is that an already-existing being, who could have a happy life, is prevented from having a happy life?I think it’s still an open question. It would be a tragic loss if our species became extinct, but how do we compare that tragedy with tragedies that might occur now to a billion people? I can’t give a good answer to that. I think it could be reasonable to say, “No, we should focus on the present, where we’re going to have greater confidence in what we’re doing,” than focus on the long-term distant future.

What’s the answer? I think it’s still an open question. It would be a tragic loss if our species became extinct, but how do we compare that tragedy with tragedies that might occur now to a billion people? I can’t give a good answer to that. I think it could be reasonable to say, “No, we should focus on the present, where we’re going to have greater confidence in what we’re doing,” than focus on the long-term distant future.


I’m just a ding-dong, but it seems that there are common-sense objections to longtermism. It’s like, if I see a fire in my yard that I could put out and save some people, shouldn’t I obviously do that rather than say, “Well, I’m working on a fire-retardant system that could save millions of lives at some undefined point in the future”? It runs into what appears to be a common-sense problem, because our intuitions obviously are to help the people now. We’ve evolved to deal with problems that are right there and now. Our ancestors survived because they dealt with those problems. They didn’t survive because they had strong intuitions that we ought to act for the distant future — because there was nothing they could do about the distant future. We are now in a position where we have more influence on whether there will be a human future, so I’m inclined not to trust those common-sense intuitions. But my answer would be: Sure, you should put out the fire. Not because that’s just your common-sense intuition but because you can be highly confident that you can do a lot of good there, and anyway, you can put out the fire and go back to your work on the fire retardant tomorrow.

Not trusting common-sense intuitions is sort of Peter Singer’s whole bag. I think that’s right. Don’t trust your intuitions to think that you ought to help your neighbors in your affluent community rather than distant people elsewhere in the world that you can’t relate to; don’t trust your intuitions in thinking that it’s only humans that matter or human suffering that is always a higher priority than nonhuman animal suffering. I’m somewhat skeptical about trusting those moral intuitions.


You take these moral intuitions about things that people hold closely, like what we eat or how we spend our money, or even the notion that we’re good, and you say, “Hold on a second, are you really behaving ethically?” Where do you think your impulse to do that comes from? It came gradually. I started thinking about particular issues where it was obvious that you could reduce suffering but people had intuitive reasons for not doing so. One of those was the area of biomedical ethics. I was interested in issues about death and dying, and I’ve for a long time been a supporter of medical assistance in dying. When I started talking to people about that, especially doctors, they would say, “Look, it’s all right for us to allow people who are suffering to die by not treating them, but we can’t cross that line and actually assist them in dying.” And I would say, “Well, why?” That example is one where I was critical of intuitions. They were perhaps religiously based intuitions. The fact that I wasn’t religious may have led me to challenge those intuitions. But then I started thinking about a whole range of other intuitions that were probably not religious but may be based in what helped our ancestors to survive.


I was reading the academic journal that you coedit, The Journal of Controversial Ideas. The idea behind the journal is to give rigorous academic treatment and platform to ideas that might be seen as beyond the pale. There are plenty of what seem to me to be relevant arguments in the journal to do with things like public health and academia. And then there are pieces about when blackface should be allowed or arguing for zoophilia — bestiality. Who’s clamoring for deeper arguments in support of these things? What is the point other than provocation? I think both those issues, although they’re certainly far less significant than many of the issues that articles in the journal discuss, have some significance. The question about blackface is relevant to drawing lines about what are people going to get criticized for. The article takes a nuanced approach to that. It acknowledges that there would be cases in which using blackface would be offensive and inappropriate, but it also refers to other cases in which it’s not objectionable. So if people are going to be outed in some way for doing this, and it happened to Justin Trudeau, then you do need to say, what are the cases in which this is not such a bad thing to do? And the case of zoophilia —


Yeah, tell me that one. Well, people go to jail for this, and they may not be causing any harm. It’s reasonable, if somebody’s going to be sent to prison, to ask: “Have you harmed any sentient being? Should this be a crime? Why should it be a crime?” Now, there’s maybe a very small number of cases that would get prosecuted, but I think that’s enough justification for airing the issue.


People have criticized you for not taking into account aspects of personal experience about which you might be ignorant. The example I’m thinking of is your idea that parents should have the right to terminate babies born with severe disabilities that might cause them to suffer terribly. Critics say that you can’t wrap your head around the fact that lives very different from your own might be just as valuable or involve as much happiness, and that some of your ideas also might be stigmatizing or objectifying to nonnormative bodies. Is there anything to the criticism that rationally theorizing from a distance is missing something essential? Rationally theorizing from a distance easily can miss something essential, certainly, but I don’t think that applies to my views about these cases. I formed those views after having discussions not only with doctors in charge of treating infants born with severe disabilities but also some of the parents of those infants, of those children who were no longer infants. I had discussed this with a number of people, both in person and in letters that I had from people. I remember one who said, “The doctors got to play with their toys” — meaning their surgical equipment and their skills — “at helping my son to survive, and then they handed the baby over to us, and the result has been that my child has suffered for nine years.” I do find it strange that some people in the disability movement who are mentally as gifted as anyone but happen to be in wheelchairs think that the fact that they are in a wheelchair gives them greater insight into what it’s like to be a child with severe disabilities that are not just physical but also mental. Or what it’s like to be the parents of children like that.


I don’t know that they’re saying that it gives them particular insights into that specific example. I think they’re saying they might have specific insights into what it’s like to live a different kind of life that you don’t have and can’t access. That’s true, but that’s generally not the kind of case that I’m talking about in suggesting that parents ought to have the option of euthanasia in cases of very severe disabilities.


Is there any way in which airing your more controversial philosophical views has been detrimental to your larger project? This is the idea that people might be turned off by what Peter Singer has to say about people with disabilities, and therefore they’re not going to pay attention to what he has to say about animal rights. There is a possible trade-off, yes, but it’s difficult as a philosopher, because I get asked these questions, and if I start to prevaricate or be fuzzy about the answer, my reputation as a philosopher falls. It’s important to try to follow the argument wherever it goes. There may be some cost to it, but it’s hard to balance those costs against the fact that you’re regarded as a rigorous, clear-thinking philosopher, and people pay more attention to what you say for that reason.

I read your memoir [“Pushing Time Away”]: Three of your four grandparents died at the hands of the Nazis in the Holocaust. And about your grandfather, David Oppenheim, who was a collaborator of Freud’s, you wrote that he spent his life trying to understand his fellow human beings yet seems to have failed to take the Nazi threat to the Jews seriously enough; maybe he had “too much confidence in human reason.” Do you see your grandfather’s work and your work as interacting with or paralleling each other in any way? Possibly paralleling, but not really interacting, because I didn’t read my grandfather’s work until the late 1990s, and I’d already written “Animal Liberation,” I’d already written “Practical Ethics,” I’d already written “Rethinking Life and Death.” What you could point to, I suppose, would be that some of my grandfather’s general attitudes were passed down to me by my mother. That would include the fact that I’m not religious. Some of that did get passed down to me. But not in terms of my specific views about suffering. Now, were they influenced by the knowledge of the suffering that the Nazis inflicted on my grandparents and other members of my extended family and on my parents by driving them out of their home in Vienna? That might have led to why trying to prevent unnecessary suffering has been a leading impulse in the work that I’ve written.

But do you think it did lead to that? I honestly don’t know. I don’t have the self-awareness to say to what extent was knowledge of the Holocaust background in my family decisive in leading me in that direction.


This is a self-awareness question: When your mom was dying from Alzheimer’s — It was some form of dementia. I don’t know if it was Alzheimer’s.

You spent a fair amount of money on providing care toward the end of her life. Which is obviously completely understandable. But was that the most utilitarian use of your money? And if not, did that teach you something about the limits of rational thinking when it comes to helping people? It was probably not the most utilitarian thing to do with those resources, but there would have been personal cost to me. Both in thinking I hadn’t looked after my mother, and also, I had a sister — if I had said, “You can pay for our mother’s care, but I’m not going to,” that would have totally disrupted the warm relationship that I had with my sister. Now, you could argue the money could have helped many people in important ways, and therefore I was being, in a sense, self-interested in not wanting to cause that family rupture. That gets to your second question: Does it show there are limits? Yes, I think there are. Certainly, I’m aware that there are limits to things that I am prepared to do in order to produce the greatest good.

Are those limits a version of common sense? I think they’re a version of what we can reasonably expect people to do. Maybe it’s not good to ask people to do more than we can reasonably expect them to do. There’s a distinction between what would be the right thing to do to the extent that we act in a perfectly ethical way and what is the right thing to ask others to do, perhaps even to do yourself, that might take more account of the fact that we are not perfectly rational, perfectly ethical beings.

One of the things I find myself struggling with about your ideas relates to what the philosopher Derek Parfit called “the repugnant conclusion”: If you follow some of your ideas through to their logical conclusions, you can wind up in morally disturbing places. An example would be — tell me if I’m wrong — that according to your thinking a large number of people with lives barely worth living could be considered better than a smaller number of people living great lives. Your response to that is what? That it’s unlikely we’d ever follow these ideas through to their logical conclusions? My response on that particular case is that that’s not my clear view. I’m still somewhat open minded on that issue. But maybe you’re asking a broader question about whether I hold views that leave me uncomfortable in some way. And, yes, there are views that I hold that leave me quite uncomfortable.

Like what? Views about distribution of well-being. Suppose that you have the choice of helping people who are very badly off by a small amount or helping people who are reasonably well off by a much larger amount, and you can’t do both. You can imagine cases where you spend a vast amount of resources making a small number of people who are really badly off slightly better off, or you make, let’s say, 95 percent of the population significantly better off. I think the right thing to do is to make 95 percent of the population significantly better off. But I’m uncomfortable about the thought that there are people who are worse off, and you could help them, but you don’t.


Not in a thought-experiment way. In a practical, real-life way. In a practical, real-life way, punishing people who are really evil and have done horrible things — using the death penalty. I can feel the pull of that. I feel the retributive sense of that. But I’m not a retributivist, and I think the punishment has to be justified in terms of its consequences, not just the fact that a bad person is now dead.


I suspect most people see themselves as, on balance, a net good for the world. But how does someone know? Very few people are doing enough to make the world a better place. They’re probably not. I don’t think that I’m doing enough to make the world a better place. But how would you know? You would look around for other ways of doing more to make the world a better place, and you would say, “There aren’t any.” That’s the extreme position.


Where’s the line short of that? The line short of that is to say: “I’m doing a lot more than the current social standard is. I’m trying to raise that standard. I’m setting an example of doing more than the current standard.” If you can say those things, you can be content with what you’re doing.