Monday, September 30, 2024

3652. Socialism of the Twenty First Century

By Kamran Nayeri, June 23, 2022
Anthropocentriam vs. Ecocentrism

Editor's Note: This essay was first published in June 2022 in Farsi in the socialist website نقد اقتصاد سیاسی ("Critique of Political Economy)" edited by Parviz Sedaghat in Tehran, Iran. The free translation from Farsi into English is mine. 

*     *     *

Hollywood capitalized on simmering concerns about the existential crises facing humanity with the film " Don't Look Up " (2021). The summary of the movie is as follows. Two scientists discovered that a comet is on a collision course with Earth in the next six months. This collision could cause mass extinction on the planet. When they go to the government and the mass media, they see the indifference of the authorities and ordinary people. Attempts to destroy the comet in time with a nuclear missile fail and the comet collides with the Earth, causing a mass extinction. However, the President of the United States and a select group of 2,000 people manages to escape in a rocket that was launched before the comet hit. After a journey of 22,740 years, they land on a green planet and end their cryogenic sleep. They exit the spaceship praising their new habitable world. But the president is suddenly killed by a bird-like hunter and others are surrounded by a group of them.

This film was welcomed by many liberal and left-leaning audiences as a way to draw attention to the existential crises that humanity is currently facing - catastrophic climate change, the Sixth extinction, ongoing pandemics and nuclear holocaust.

However, the film revolves around a natural disaster, but all current existential crises are anthropogenic (human-caused) and are rooted in our social system, the anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization. Unlike the movie, where the comet can be destroyed by a nuclear missile, a technological solution managed by the military and scientific staff and the capitalist state, the actual existential threats facing humanity cannot be solved by mere technologies, technocrats and bureaucrats, and the capitalist state. It will require an ecological socialism through self-organization and self-activity of billions of working people.

In this essay, I will critically outline the salient features of 19th and 20th century socialisms before I outline what I believe to be the salient features of 21st century ecological. I will conclude the essay with the need to develop a new materialism in which all beings have agency, a new theory of history with a new set of historical actors, and a new vision of post-capitalist society.

Part 1. Socialism of the nineteenth century

Historical materialism and its application to the analysis of the capitalist mode of production provides Marx with his theory of human liberation from alienation. The common mistaken view is that Marx’s theory focuses liberation of the working class from capitalist exploitation ignores that in Marx alienation is ontologically and historically prior and more fundamental than exploitation. To exploit the others, they (human or non-human) must first be alienated, to become the "other," the object rather than the subject. As Marx argues, "Human emotions, thoughts, etc., are not merely anthropological phenomena in the [more limited sense of the word] but are truly ontological affirmations of existence [nature] (Marx, 1844).”

However, when getting rid of alienation became Marx's philosophical and theoretical starting point, a historical answer was required. As MészMezsarosáros (1970: p. 36) explains:

“If man has become ‘alienated,’ he must have been alienated from something, as a result of certain causes - the interaction of events and conditions in relation to man as the subject of this alienation - which manifest themselves in a historical framework. Similarly, ‘escape from alienation’ is an inherently historical concept that embodies the successful realization of a process that leads to a qualitatively different state of affairs.”

Marx's vision of socialism free association of direct producers; as an abundant society that eliminates material needs, where individual’s freedom is a condition for freedom of all required a completely unalienated society without commodities, money, wage labor, and the state, all of which are considered forms of alienation, exploitation, and oppression.

I follow the suggestions of Mendel (1971; chapter 11) and Mézsáros (1970) to outline the salient features of Marx's theory of socialism. I begin with Marx's turn from philosophy to the critique of political economy in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844. This led to Marx's definitive break with Young Hegelians and the materialism of Feuerbach in Theses on Feuerbach (1845) and The German Ideology (1845-1846), the latter was written in collaboration with Engels and outlined their theory of history, historical materialism. Subsequently, Marx applied the methodology of historical materialism to the analysis of the capitalist mode of production. The first volume of Capital was published in 1867, and after his death, Engels edited the second volume (1885) and the third volume (1894); and Karl Kautsky edited the three-volume Theories of Surplus Value (written in 1863 and edited and published in 1905-1910). Engels (1883) considered historical materialism and theory of surplus value to be Marx's key intellectual contributions. At the same time he emphasized that Marx was first and above all a revolutionary socialist. Marx himself recounts parts of his intellectual development in his "Preface" to the A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (1859). I take this standard reading as the basis for the discussion of Marxian theory in this essay.

Historical materialism

Class struggle as motor force in historiography and the idea of ​​progressive stages in the historical development of society were present in intellectual history of Europe before Marx and Engels. The concept of class struggle goes back at least to the time of Giovanni Battista Vico (1668-1744). The idea of ​​developmental stages in history dates to at least the 18th century. Ronald (1976/2010) quotes Efimovich Desnistky , a former student of Adam Smith in 1761, who described the four stages of historical evolution in a 1781 university lecture in Moscow. He described them as hunting and gathering, pastoralism, agriculture and commerce. (Meek, 1976/2010: p. 5). Desnistky then goes on to state: “This origin and upward course of human society is common among all primitive people. According to these four conditions of the people, we must deduce their history, government, laws and customs and measure their various successes in sciences and arts. (quoted by Meek, ibid.) Meek attributes the first written discussions about the theory of four stages to Montesquieu (1689-1755), Smith (1723-1790), and Turgot (1727-1781).

Graeber and Wengro (2021: pp. 60-61) have argued that Turgut developed the theory of stages of social development because of Native American influence on European thought. They detail the influence of Wengrow people in the New French Canada on French colonists in the 17th century and, through them and directly on native travelers to Europe, on European culture and society at the time, particularly the European intellectual development in particular the Enlightenment. In fact, they argue that Smith borrowed the theory of stages of history from Turgot.

Thus, the basic ideas for the historical materialism of Marx and Engels were present in the writings of the authors they studied closely in previous decades. Their contribution lies in combining these ideas into a superior theory of history. Charles Darwin developed his theory of evolution by natural selection in a similar way.

In building the theory of historical materialism, Marx and Engels relied on a kind of materialist ontology of human nature that distinguished them from the dominant liberal-bourgeois idealist idea of ​​human nature: "Human nature is not an abstraction that is placed inside each individual. In reality, this essence is nothing but the sum of social relations (Marx, 1845, the sixth thesis). They also defined their materialism by privileging "social humanity" and focusing on collective class actors as opposed to individual actors in history: "The scene of old materialism is civil society, while the new view [of materialism] is human society or social humanity (Ibid: the tenth thesis).” According to Mézsáros (1970: p. 39) "a very important point is whether ... the question of ‘human nature’ is measured within an implicitly or explicitly ‘egalitarian’ explanatory framework."

It must be remembered that Marx and Engels' knowledge of history was limited to the published historiography available at the time, which covered about 3,000 years (see endnote 1).

“This mode of production must not be considered simply as being the production of the physical existence of the individuals. Rather it is a definite form of activity of these individuals, a definite form of expressing their life, a definite mode of life on their part. As individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore, coincides with their production, both with what they produce and with how they produce. The nature of individuals thus depends on the material conditions determining their production (Marx and Engels, 1945).”

Thus, historical materialism was deliberately anthropocentric because it focused on the evolution of human society in abstraction from nature and was based on what Marx and Engels knew about history, which was at most 3,000 years old. Today we know that humanity (Homo sapiens) is at least 300 thousand years old. In fact, our history is actually rooted in the human species (Homo genus) which arose more than 2.8 million years ago (fire was controlled and used by Homo eractus about one million years ago.

The theory of the proletariat as a universal class

Nor was it Marx and Engels who first discovered the revolutionary potential of the proletariat. As Hal Draper (1971) points out: " When Marx and Engels were crystallizing their views on this subject, the revolutionary potentialities of the proletariat were already being recognized here and there.”  Draper points to Robert Owen and Saint-Simon theories of socialism.

What was new in Marx's theory of the proletariat was the idea that the proletariat is not a mere object, a "class in itself," but that it can become a "class for itself" in its struggle with the bourgeoisie. Marx argued that when the proletariat comes to power, it will act as the universal class destroying the rule of capital and all vestiges of class society (all based on alienation) in a transition period leading to a classless and non-aliened society, i.e. socialism. Therefore, the concept of self-organization and self-mobilization of the working class became the cornerstone of Marx's theory of socialism.

In the “Rules and Administrative Regulations of the International Workingmen’s Association” (First International) Marx (1864) provided the most concise version of this view as : “That the emancipation of the working classes must be conquered by the working classes themselves; that, the struggle for the emancipation of the working classes means not a struggle for class privileges and monopolies, but for equal rights and duties, and the abolition of all class rule.”

The idea of ​​the proletariat as a "universal class" for the liberation of humanity appears in Marx's "Introduction" A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right (Marx 1843) in a philosophical context. In the same text, Marx himself admits that "The proletariat is beginning to appear in Germany as a result of the rising industrial movement.” However, he continues:

“In Germany, no form of bondage can be broken without breaking all forms of bondage. Germany, which is renowned for its thoroughness, cannot make a revolution unless it is a thorough one. The emancipation of the German is the emancipation of man. The head of this emancipation is philosophy, its heart the proletariat. Philosophy cannot realize itself without the transcendence [Aufhebung] of the proletariat, and the proletariat cannot transcend itself without the realization [Verwirklichung] of philosophy (Marx, 1843).” (see endnote 2)

It took decades for the proletariat to become a social force in Germany. German reunification took place 28 years later in 1871, and it was still decades away to create an industrial working class through.

There are theoretical and empirical tensions in Marx's theory of the proletariat. At the theoretical level, the principle of the right to self-determination implies the ability to generalize from practical struggles; that is, the development of a revolutionary theory to overcome capitalism and transition to socialism by the self-organized and self-mobilizing proletariat. On July 1,1874, Engels mentions this issue in his "Appendix to the Preface" to the Peasants' War in Germany (1850). He argued that German workers enjoyed two important advantages compared to the rest of Europe.

“First, they belong to the most theoretical people in Europe; Second, they have retained that theoretical tact that the so-called "educated" people of Germany have completely lost. Without German philosophy, especially Hegel's philosophy, German scientific socialism (the only existing scientific socialism) would never have come into existence. Without theoretical tact, scientific socialism would never have become the flesh and blood of the workers.

“The second advantage is that, chronologically, the Germans were the last to enter the labor movement. In the same way that German theoretical socialism never forgets that it rests on the shoulders of Saint-Simon, Fourier and Owen, a trio who, in spite of their utopianism and fanciful ideas, were among the most wonderful minds of all history, and whose genius foresaw many things that proved to be true. Now scientifically proven, the German practical labor movement must never forget that it grew on the shoulders of the movements of England and France, benefited from their experience gained at a heavy price, and was therefore in a position to recover from their mistakes. which were inevitable in their time, to avoid. Without the trade unions of England and the political struggles of the French workers before the German labor movement, without the powerful impetus of the Paris Commune, where would we be now (England, 1874) ?”

In short, Engels here argues in favor of a highly developed "scientific" theory of socialism that combines philosophy, socialist theory, and labor and socialist history. However, Engels does not discuss how this "theory of scientific socialism" will develop over time and how will it be preserved and shared among the generations.

I will return to this question when I discuss Lenin's vanguard party theory.

The second tension in the Marxist theory of the proletariat is the rise of the labor aristocracy. Marx and Engels, who spent the latter part of their lives in England, wrote about the emergence of an English labor aristocracy that complicated their theory of the proletariat and socialist revolution (Nayeri 2005; Draper 1978, pp. 105-110). In a letter to Karl Liebknecht, Marx wrote:

“The English working class had been gradually more and more deeply demoralized by the period of corruption since 1848 and had at last got to the point when they were nothing more than the tail of the great Liberal Party, i.e., henchmen of the capitalists. Their direction had gone completely into the hands of the corrupt trade union leaders and professional agitators (Marx, February 11, 1878).”

Engels, who lived longer, wrote more widely about this. In the 1892 Preface to the German edition of The Condition of the Working Class in England (1845), he wrote of

"[T]echnical workers, carpenters, plumbers, and builders" whose conditions had improved dramatically in the last four decades.

“They form an aristocracy among the working class who have managed to carve out a relatively comfortable position for themselves and accept it as an end. They are exemplary workers ... and indeed very pleasant people today, for any sensible capitalist in particular and for the whole class of capitalists in general.

“The truth is: during the period of British industrial monopoly, the working class shared in some of its benefits. These benefits were distributed among them very unequally; The privileged minority pocketed more, but even the masses of workers also took at least a temporary share from time to time. That is why there has been no news of socialism in England since the death of Owenism (England, 1892).”

Clearly, the Marxist theory of the proletariat as a universal revolutionary class needed further development. The matter became more serious because of the lack of Marx's key early writings related to alienation and the Grundrisse. These were first published in 1939-1941. (see endnote 3) However, other important developments played a role in the theories of socialism that followed which significantly deviated from Marx's.

With the emergence of labor aristocracy in the capitalist industrial countries provided the basis for the emergence of social democratic reformism. Marx's theory about the capitalist mode of production (the labor theory of value or the "law of value") was replace with Hilferding’s finance/monopoly capital giving more power to the corporation and the state who presumably dominated the market; Lenin revised Marx's theory of the proletariat with his vanguard party theory, and with the degeneration of the October 1917 socialist revolution in Russia in the 1920s led to the rise of Stalinism. As a result, the world revolution was diverted from the centers of industrial capitalism to the mainly agrarian cultural countries on the periphery of world economy where the peasantry, not the proletariat, was the key social class. The revolutions of the twentieth century were essentially revolutions of the colonial and semi-colonial peoples. Those that its leaderships fell in the hands of the Stalinist parties claimed socialism as their goal and replicated the Soviet Union model under Joseph Stalin.

The rise of Marxism as a “scientific" doctrine

Karl Kautsky, who was the prominent theoretician of the German Social Democratic Party, in his conflict with Bernstein's reformism accused him of violating the principles of "Marxism." In 1882, Engels had criticized the use of the word "Marxism," noting that Marx himself, when discussing Paul Lafargue, a self-proclaimed "Marxist," objected to the terminology saying that if Lafargue's views were Marxist "one thing is certain and that is that I am not a Marxist (Haupt et al., 2010).”

However, the label of Marxism was applied to key trends in twentieth-century socialism: social democracy, Stalinism, and Trotskyism. The claim that the teachings of Marx and Engels were scientific originated with Engels and especially with his popular pamphlet, Socialism: Scientific and Utopian. Engels initially used the term "scientific" because their vision of socialism was derived from their historical materialism, not as a utopia (although, as I will argue, this vision is also utopian (Engels 1880). I have shown (Nayeri 2021) that historical materialism can be considered scientific in the light of Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of the Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) because it caused a fundamental change in the basic concepts and empirical procedures of historiography. Roy Bhaskar (1979; 1994) has argued that Marx 's Capital can be considered scientific according to the findings of scientific realism. However, Engels' claim is not based on such arguments in philosophy of science or philosophy of social sciences. His claim was purely ideological, as it remains to this day. As the teachings of Marx and Engels became a "scientific" doctrine, a fundamental change occurred in relation to the agency of the proletariat in the theory of socialist revolution and the relationship between the socialist movement and the labor movement. The proletariat became the mass that the vanguard parties had to lead. The parties themselves, in tun,  have been supposed to be led by a leadership who is supposed to know the accepted doctrine well. A division of labor occurred within these parties between the leadership and the rank and file, as the leaders were assumed to be the holders and interpreters of the scared doctrine who dealt with the "big issues." The rank and file were responsible for the day-to-day tasks of the party.  It is no wonder that cults of personality often develop in such centralized parties.

Reformism of the Second International

The Social Democratic Party of Germany (SDP) was the largest party in the Second International and the most influential in the labor movement. Unfortunately, as Bolshevik leader Grigory Zinoviev documented in The Social Roots of Opportunism (1916), the SDP also turned out to be the party of the labor aristocracy. After reviewing the official statistics of SDP, he wrote:

“According to our calculation, 4,000 functionaries occupy at least 12,000 – if not more – important party and trade union functions. Every more or less efficient functionary takes care simultaneously of two to three and often even more offices. He is at the same time a Reichstag deputy and an editor, a member of the Landtag and a party secretary, the president of a trade union, an editor, a cooperative functionary, a city councilman, etc. Thus all power in the party and trade unions accumulates in the hands of this upper 4,000. (The salaries accumulate, too. Many of the officials of the labor movement receive 10,000 marks and over per year.) The whole business depends upon them. They hold in their hands the whole powerful apparatus of the press, of the organization of the mutual aid societies, the entire electoral apparatus, etc. (Zinoviev, 1916).”

Finance Capital

The change in the social composition of the German SPD leadership coincided with a fundamental revision of Marx's theory about the capitalist mode of production. In his highly influential book Finance Capital (1910), Rudolf Hilferding argued that Marx's labor theory of value (the "law of value") was rendered obsolete by the rise of finance capital or monopoly capitalism. He presented a systematic analysis of the changing nature of capitalist development in the 19th century, especially in Germany. The analysis of competition is the main objective of the third section entitled "Financial Capital and the Limits of Free Competition". Hilferding reaches the logical conclusion of his critique that Marx's labor theory of value no longer works:

“Classical economics conceives price as the expression of the anarchic character of social production, and the price level as depending upon the social productivity of labour. But the objective law of price can operate only through competition. If monopolistic combinations abolish competition, they eliminate at the same time the only means through which an objective law of price can actually prevail. Price ceases to be an objectively determined magnitude and becomes an accounting exercise for those who decide what it shall be by fiat, a presupposition instead of a result, subjective rather than objective, something arbitrary and accidental rather than a necessity which is independent of the will and consciousness of the parties concerned. It seems that the monopolistic combine, while it confirms Marx's theory of concentration, at the same time tends to undermine his theory of value (Hilferding 2010).”

What will replace the laws of motion of Marx's capitalist system in financial capital? Hilferding believed that the amalgamation of the public cartel with the capitalist state would lead to "organized capitalism." He argued in defense of the reformist path of social democracy:

“Organized capitalism means replacing free competition with the social principle of planned production. The task of the current generation of social democrats is to call for government assistance to transform this economy under the organization and direction of the capitalists into an economy under the direction of the democratic state. (Hilferding quoted by Green (1990, p. 203).”

That is, socialism was redefined as state socialism, and the class character of the state was determined by the party in power! That is, if socialists came to power through elections they could use the state apparatus to achieve "socialist" goals. Social democratic policies eventually contributed to the development of capitalist welfare states in Western Europe.

The history of socialist theorizing of capitalism after Hilferding is marked by a split between a small minority who believe that Marx's theory of competition still operated and his labor theory of value is still valid, and an influential majority, including the parties of the Second International, Third International and Fourth International, who believed in the emergence of a type of monopoly capitalism. Some in the second category have openly claimed that Marx's law of value no longer applies, most of them have backed away from this very important conclusion of their theory. (see endnote 4)

In the 1970s, Marxist economists rediscovered that Marx's theory of free competition was fundamentally different from the neoclassical theory of "perfect competition" that a long line of Marxist theorists, from Hilferding to Paul Baran and Paul Sweezy (1966) believed to be identical. One of the pioneers of this rediscovery, Anwar Sheikh, spent four decades transforming U.S. national accounts categories into Marxian ones to provide a Marxist empirical study of U.S. economic performance based on the law of value (Sheikh and Tanak 2010; Sheikh , 2016) from the Marxist point of view. Theories of finance capital and monopoly capitalism that came after, including the theories of Bukharin and Lenin, were based on a serious misunderstanding of Marx's theory and led to important theoretical and political mistakes, including the theories of dependency and support for the "national bourgeoisie" of the latecomers to the global capitalist market. (Nayeri August 20181991/2023B Chapters 1, 3, 4).

Lenin's vanguard party theory

Lenin in "What should be done?" (1902) cites Engels' July 1, 1874, "Appendix to the Preface" to The Peasants' War in Germany (1850), cited above, to argue for building a party based on proletarian democratic centralism. Claiming that no revolutionary movement can exist without a revolutionary theory, Lenin continued to argue:

“We have said that there could not have been Social-Democratic consciousness among

the workers. It would have to be brought to them from without. The history of all countries shows that the working class, exclusively by its own effort, is able to develop only trade union consciousness… The theory of socialism, however, grew out of the philosophic, historical,

and economic theories elaborated by educated representatives of the propertied classes,

by intellectuals. By their social status the founders of modern scientific socialism, Marx

and Engels, themselves belonged to the bourgeois intelligentsia. In the very same way, in

Russia, the theoretical doctrine of Social-Democracy arose altogether independently of the spontaneous growth of the working-class movement; it arose as a natural and inevitable outcome of the development of thought among the revolutionary socialist intelligentsia. In the period under discussion, the middle nineties, this doctrine not only represented the completely formulated program of the Emancipation of Labour group, but had already won over to its side the majority of the revolutionary youth in Russia.” (ibid.)

There are three key points about Lenin's vanguard party theory. First, it is a clear break from Marx's own (given that Marx and Engels did not have the opportunity to revise their theory of the proletariat as a universal class in light of the rise of the labor aristocracy in Britain and elsewhere).

Second, the Bolshevik Party played an important role in the Russian revolutions However, as China Mieville (2017; for review, see Nayeri December 2017) brilliantly recounts the events from February to October, focusing on the role played by the soviets, the mutually reinforcing interaction of the self-organized and self-mobilization Russian proletariat with the Bolshevik Party resulted in the first workers’ state in history. The centrality of the role played by self-organized and self-mobilizing Soviets was recognized in Lenin's April Theses (April 1917) and the Bolsheviks' adoption of the slogan "All power to the soviets" in May (Lih July 2017). Lenin argued in The State and Revolution (August–September 1917) that the Soviets formed the backbone of a workers' state. However, the tension in Lenin's own mind is revealed in the full title of the pamphlet, which is The State and Revolution and the Tasks of the Proletariat in the Revolution.  In Lenin's mind it is the party that sets the task for the class, even though basing himself on Marx’s teaching that the Soviets should form the future workers' state!

Thirdly, the Bolshevik Party as conceived by Lenin did not last for more than 20 years and turned into its opposite, a Stalinist party. Since then, no party like Lenin's party has been created. The problem of elevating the party to the top of the power structure during the transition period from capitalism to socialism was undermined by the rising Stalinist bureaucracy. As the self-organized and self-mobilizing organs of working people's power declined and disbanded after the outbreak of the Civil War in 1918, the hoped-for revolutions in Europe failed, and the young Soviet Republic faced the destruction of much of its productive capacity, bureaucracy began to proliferate. Bureaucracy began to grow within society, the state and the party. In 1922-1923, suffering from a stroke, Lenin waged a political struggle against the policies of the growing bureaucracy headed by Joseph Stalin (Lenin, 2010).  In his The Revolution Betrayed: What Is the Soviet Union and Where Is It going?” Trotsky (1936) wrote:

“The present doctrine that Bolshevism does not tolerate factions is a myth of epoch decline. In reality the history of Bolshevism is a history of the struggle of factions. And, indeed, how could a genuinely revolutionary organization, setting itself the task of overthrowing the world and uniting under its banner the most audacious iconoclasts, fighters and insurgents, live and develop without intellectual conflicts, without groupings and temporary factional formations? The farsightedness of the Bolshevik leadership often made it possible to soften conflicts and shorten the duration of factional struggle, but no more than that. The Central Committee relied upon this seething democratic support. From this it derived the audacity to make decisions and give orders. The obvious correctness of the leadership at all critical stages gave it that high authority which is the priceless moral capital of centralism (Trotsky 1936).”

He added:

“The very center of Lenin's attention and that of his colleagues was occupied by a continual concern to protect the Bolshevik ranks from the vices of those in power. However, the extraordinary closeness and at times actual merging of the party with the state apparatus had already in those first years done indubitable harm to the freedom and elasticity of the party regime. Democracy had been narrowed in proportion as difficulties increased. In the beginning, the party had wished and hoped to preserve freedom of political struggle within the framework of the Soviets. The civil war introduced stern amendments into this calculation. The opposition parties were forbidden one after the other. This measure, obviously in conflict with the spirit of Soviet democracy, the leaders of Bolshevism regarded not as a principle, but as an episodic act of self-defense (ibid.).”

Trotsky explained how these temporary anti-democratic decisions were used by Stalin as the leader of the rising bureaucratic caste as “Leninism” as a compliment to his “theory” of socialism in one country. “Together with the theory of socialism in one country, there was put into circulation by the bureaucracy a theory that in Bolshevism the Central Committee is everything and the party nothing. This second theory was in any case realized with more success than the first (ibid.)”

Thus, the parties of the Communist International became bureaucratic hierarchies and wherever Stalinists came to power they created one-party states that kept the political life of the country under its control.

Thus, Lenin's vanguard party lasted only about two decades before turning into its opposite. In the hundred years since its destruction, there has never been another revolutionary socialist party like it.

Trotsky's characterization of the Soviet Union as a workers’ state was a major error. Although he admitted that "for all its pretensions, the view of the workers' state as expressed by Marx, Engels and Lenin, and the actual state now headed by Stalin, are worlds apart," Trotsky who argued Stalinism was counterrevolutionary through and through and that “the Soviet state has acquired a totalitarian-bureaucratic character.” Still. he insisted that the Soviet Union remained a workers’ state, albeit degenerated. His reasoning: the state was based on the nationalized social means of production, monopoly of foreign trade, and central planning! In other words, the fact that the proletariat was not in power did not change that character of the state! “The final physiognomy of the workers' state ought to be determined by the changing relations between its bourgeois and socialist tendencies.’”

Basing itself on this theoretical confusion, the Fourth International mistakenly recognized a number of other states led by Stalinist parties after the Second World War as workers' states albeit “deformed.” In Eastern Europe at the end of World War II in countries occupied by the Red Army, the economy and society were restructured along similar lines to the Soviet Union. In North Korea, China and Vietnam, Stalinist parties came to power after a nationalist struggle against internal reaction and imperialism.

In Cuba, Fidel Castro's 26th of July Movement, inspired by the Cuban and Latin American anti-imperialist and nationalist-democratic movements, came to power in 1959. Castro's leadership in carrying out agrarian reforms and standing up to US imperialism went to the Soviet bloc for new economic and diplomatic relations. In a speech on April 16, 1961, the day before the Bay of Pigs attack, Fidel Castro announced socialism as the goal of the Cuban revolution. As I will argue later, Cuba also became dominated by a  Stalinist Party largely because Castro mistook the Stalinist Popular Socialist Party as representing “Marxism-Leninism” in Cuba and established the Communist Party accordingly, modeled after it.

Nationalist-democratic revolutionary wars in Yugoslavia, China, Korea, Vietnam, and Cuba drew their support mainly from the peasantry. All these new states have been ruled by their respective “communist Party” in which there is not party democracy and no socialist democracy for the popular masses.  

Therefore, the socialist history of the 20th century was mainly written by the social democratic and Stalinist mass parties. Together they destroyed all revolutionary and pre-revolutionary positions in Western Europe and failed to unite their forces to prevent the rise of fascism in Germany.

Part 3. Socialism of the Twentieth First Century

Before outlining the salient features of socialism for the 21st century, let me return to the explosion of man-made ecological crises in the recent decades with which this essay began. If, as I have argued (Nayeri May 2017; October 2018; March 2020; March 2022), these ecological crises, including those that pose existential threats to humanity, are rooted in anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization. Thus, to resolve them we must transcend the existing civilization in the direction of an ecocentric socialist future.

The Anthropocene

More than two hundred sixty years since the beginning of the Industrial Revolution in England in 1760, the expansion of capitalist industrialization, especially after the Second World War, has brought us the Anthropocene (The Age of Humans). Scientists have argued, and Earth system scientists now agree, that the Holocene, the geologic epoch that began 11,700 years ago, has given way to the Anthropocene. Stratigraphers who study the precise demarcation and depositional timeline of rock layers agree. While the Holocene was characterized by a climate that supported the emergence and expansion of agricultural-based civilizations, the Anthropocene has brought us global crises that, if left unchecked, will destroy most life on planet Earth, including humanity.

Let me mention just one source about the mounting ecological crises. The Stockholm Resilience Center published a study on the planetary crisis (Rackström et al. 2009) which was updated (Steffen et al., 2015) identified nine Earth System Boundaries ("thresholds of safe operational space for human societies). Climate change and the "integrity of the biosphere" (the Sixth extinction) are set as the main boundaries "because they both cause changes in other things and are affected by those changes." The nine boundaries are:

1. Climate changes

2. Changes in biosphere integrity (i.e. the Sixth extinction)

3. Destruction of stratospheric ozone layer

4. Ocean acidification

5. Biogeochemical flows (phosphorus and nitrogen cycles)

6. Land system change (e.g, deforestation)

7. Scarcity of fresh water

8. Aerosol loading of the atmosphere (microscopic particles in the atmosphere that affect the weather and living organisms)

9. Introducing new entities (such as organic pollutants, radioactive substances, nanomaterials, and microplastics).

The Great Acceleration (2015), a report by the International Geosphere-Biosphere Program concludes:

“Global change does not operate in isolation but rather interacts with an almost bewildering array of natural variability modes, and, also with other human-driven effects at many scales. Especially important are those cases where interacting stresses cause a threshold to be crossed and a rapid change in state or functioning to occur.
.”

This paper cites data on exponential human population growth, urbanization, real GDP growth, foreign direct investment, primary energy consumption, large dams, air travel and tourism, water consumption, paper production, fertilizer consumption, transportation, telecommunications, emissions. Carbon dioxide, methane, nitrogen dioxide, surface temperature, stratospheric ozone, marine fisheries, ocean acidification, coastal nitrogen, shrimp aquaculture, tropical forest loss, land cultivation, and destruction of the Earth's biosphere since 1750 or since data for It shows that they were collected for the first time. Clearly, these trends, if left uncheckedto their own devices, point to future ecological collapse.

Ecocentric Socialism

Ecological existential threats immediately suggest that the socialism of the 21st century must be ecological. As I have discussed above, Marx and Engels consciously set aside humanity's interaction with and dependence on nature in their construction of historical materialism to focus attention on class struggle and the role of the proletariat in socialist revolution. Thus, they wrote in The German Ideology:

“Of course, here we cannot deal with the actual physical nature of man, nor with the natural conditions in which he finds himself - that is, geological, hydrographic, climatic conditions, etc. Writing history should always start from these natural foundations and their changes in the course of history through the actions of humans. (emphasis is mine).”

With the development of the environmentalist movement in response to these crises, some socialist thinkers and currents provided a response. Some of them have added environmentalist planks to their political platform. Others have now call themselves ecological socialists (ecosocialists) to indicate their interest and attention to ecological issues. Fewer have gone so far as to formulate ecological socialist theories to explicitly incorporate nature into socialist theorizing, often using an interpretation of Marx's work (e.g. O'Connor1998; Kovel 2002; Foster 2002; Foster, Clarke and York2010; Lowy 2015; Moore 2015).

Socialist and ecological socialist theories deliberately focus on "capitalism" and the latter focuses on tendencies in "capitalism" that cause environmental degradation and lead to ecological crises. Most of them have argued that Marx's theory needs modifications to deal with ecological crises. Citing Marx's ecological insights (Burkett 1999; Foster, 2000) in his discussion of 'metabolic rift' Foster et al . have claimed that Marx's theory is inherently ecological. However, despite their different interpretations of Marx and theoretical differences all these authors ultimately argue that capitalist accumulation (growth) is responsible for ecological crises, and some explicitly accept some form of "natural limits to growth" as the solution to the crisis.

What remains outside the scope of their investigation is any theoretical and analytical consideration of the anti-ecological tendencies of all human civilizations many of which suffered ecological crises starting with the Sumerian civilization (1900-4500 BC). They also ignore how Marx and Engels deliberately formulated historical materialism as a theory of society abstracting from nature and their explicit view is that to adequately discuss human history, one must develop a theory that is conscious of the interaction of society and nature and the ultimate dependence of man. Marx’s theory of the capitalist mode of production and socialism avoids an explicit theory of humanity embedded in nature.

Therefore, the socialist theories of the 19th and 20th centuries that I have examined above and most of the ecological socialist theories of the 21st century are essentially theories of society, because nature remains outside their theoretical framework. When nature is considered, it is usually objectified and passive. Humans remain the only agency in history. Moreover, the problem of anthropocentrism, which I have argued is a manifestation of alienation from nature, is largely ignored as key to environmental ethics (Nayeri July 2021). A recent exception is Jason W. Moore (2015) who tried unsuccessfully to revise Marx's theory about history and "capitalism" to give agency to non-human nature (Nayeri 2016).

Since 2009, I have developed what I have called Ecocentric Socialism (for a recent discussion of this, see Nayeri 2023A, 2021): a theory of socialism that builds on Marx and Engels' own proposition that human history cannot be understood in isolation from nature. In fact, we are a part of nature and depended on it for our existence and well-being. What follows are distinctive features of Ecocentric Socialism in contrast to Marx's theory of socialism. This is a work in progress and will benefit from critical contributions. The socialism of the 21st century, if it ever comes, will be conceived and built by billions of working people themselves.

Theory of history: It is necessary to formulate a new theory of history which is not based on the materialism of the 19th century but based on the materialism that gives agency to all beings. Such a theory must be based on animistic ecological materialism. (see endnote 5) From the ontological point of view, human nature will no longer be limited to the set of social relations formed by the dominant mode as in Marx but as the set of social-ecological relations that are formed based on the dynamic interrelationship of four processes:  1) the transhistorical process in which organic substances arose out of mineral substances resulting in the simplest life forms about 3.7 billion years ago; (2) recognition and appreciation of humanity in its continuity with the evolution of life on planet Earth and especially our kinship with other animals; (3) the evolution of our species, Homo sapiens , which arose about 300,000 years ago from the lineage that began with the rise of the Homo genus, which first appeared more than 2.8 million years ago; and (4) the process specific to the effects of the mode of production (similar to Marx's theory yet completely different at the same time).

A Historical Theory of Alienation: Although there is explanation of the origin of alienation in human society in Marxian theory beyond Marx's writings on capitalist forms of alienation, alienation is explained by Ecocentric Socialism beginning with early farmers who alienated other species through domestication to dominate and exploit them systematically. The farm became the first artificial ecosystem and the farmer not only managed the farm but protected it from the wildness of the surrounding nature. Thus, arose alienation from nature as the source of exploitation of nature for material gain. This process began about 12,000 years ago and has been unfolding ever since. It took the early farmers thousands of years to turn a systematic economic surplus. However, once that happened so did social differentiation causing social forms of alienation. That is the source of private property, nuclear family, and the state.

The question of agency: Instead of class struggle in Marxian theory as the motor force of history, Ecocentric Socialism starts from agency for all beings in their ecological interrelation; Including the ecological interaction of animate and inanimate nature that have shaped ecosystems and the earth as a living planet since the origin of life. Accepting class struggle in class society as a source of historical change, Ecocentric Socialism also pays attention to non-class forms of struggles inside and outside civilization, including the struggle for the rights of the Earth and non-human beings in shaping human history. Therefore, the class relations and class struggle that Marx and Engels put at the center of their theoretical and practical concerns are complemented by non-class struggles against the subjugation of nature and different strata of people. Some of these struggles, such as the struggle for equality regardless of gender, race, sexual orientation and national origin, should be considered necessary to consolidate the unity of the working people. Others are existential struggles, such as the struggle to stop and reverse the climate crisis, the ongoing Sixth extinction, and the threat of nuclear war. However, other struggles, such as the fight for animal liberation or the rights of nature and its constituent elements, contribute not only to the well-being of humans but also to the process of de-alienation and ultimately human emancipation. In brief, Ecocentric Socialism will aim to dismantle all forms of power relations. In this way, the tension between the infrastructure and the superstructure in Marx's theory is resolved by elevating the “superstructure” to the same level as the “infrastructure” and their continuous interaction as the main drivers of social change.

Analytical categories: The key analytical categories are ecological-social forces of production and destruction, eco-social relations of production and domination and the dialectical interaction of “infrastructure” and “superstructure,” which are constitute a complex interdependent matrix of relationships that give agency to all beings. Above all, it is clearly recognized that the forces of production are often also the forces of destruction. Thus, the question of development of the forces of production, which is central to dominant interpretations of historical materialism, is avoided, as is the idea of progress in the ​​Enlightenment that links the good life to ever-expanding technologies and the culture of having.

The goal: the fundamental goal of Ecocentric Socialism, like in Marxian socialism, is to liberate humanity from alienation and its consequences including oppression and exploitation. However, contrary to Marx's theory that equates human liberation with freedom from the laws of nature (e.g., Engels, 1880) and a technologically advanced affluent society based on ever-increasing division (Nayeri June 2018), Ecocentric Socialism entails a process of humanity's retreat from the current culture of having in favor of a culture of being. The cultural of having is based on acquiring material possessions as much as possible. In Ecocentric Socialism the process aims at reducing humanity's ecological footprint and at the same time produce a different matrix of necessities for human well-being and development compatible with voluntary simplicity. This process is urgently needed many in the Global North. However, in the Global South and certain groups in the Global North whose basic needs are not being met, it will be necessary to redistribute existing wealth among them. At the same time, generation of wealth will be stopped and through women's empowerment and democratic family planning, the human population will be reduced dramatically over several generations so that our collective ecological footprint across all ecosystems becomes negligible. An emancipated humanity will not produce waste. Ecocentric Socialist societies will be based on democratic stationary state localized economies with low production and low technology consistent with human development.

Environmental ethics: While Marxian socialism and 20th century socialisms and 21st century ecological socialisms are all anthropocentric and have no intrinsic environmental ethics, ecological socialism is based on the understanding that anthropocentrism is the pillar of civilization based on alienation from nature and social alienation. To overcome anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization, we must strive for ecocentrism and against anthropocentrism. Thus, Ecocentric Socialism will be a combination of social and cultural revolution by billions of human beings. However, ecocentrism is not just an intellectual point of view, but a true love for nature and for life on planet Earth: to save the world, we must love the world.

Program and Strategy: The programmatic platform of Ecocentric Socialism may differ in detail from country to country. But the general framework will be the same throughout the world. I have outlined such a program for the United States elsewhere (see Nayeri Oct. 2018, section on “Ecocentric Socialism”). Ecocentric Socialism also draws on the experiences of a century and a half of world revolution, particularly in Russia and Cuba. For example, the experience of the Bolshevik Party in helping to develop mass consciousness in an anti-capitalist and socialist direction as codified in Trotsky's Transition Program (1938), the founding document of the Fourth International. Likewise, the Cuban Revolution has provided valuable lessons (Nayeri July 2017, section titled “Lessons from the Cuban Revolution”). Most important is Ernesto Che Guevara's theoretical and political contributions (Nayeri May 1, 2024).

Feasibility: It is a challenging question to end this this discussion with the question of the feasibility of socialism in general and Ecocentric Socialism in particular in the 21st century. As I have shown, Marxian socialism has had internal and empirical contradictions.

Marx's vision was very briefly realized in the preliminary phase of the Russian revolutions of 1917 with the formation of self-organizing and self-mobilizing Soviets and the establishment of the first workers' state in history.

Filmer (1995; for discussion, see Harman2002) in a comprehensive study estimated that 2.474 billion people participated in the global non-domestic labor force in the mid-1990s. Of these, about one-fifth, i.e. 379 million people, worked in industry, 800 million in services and 1.074 million in agriculture. Therefore, there is objectively a much larger proletariat around the world to strive for and uphold socialism. Of course, as I have argued the agencies for Ecocentric Socialism are significantly different and more diverse, and include segments of the population such as women, youth, indigenous peoples, nature lovers, and so on. However, although these classes and groups are now very large, they are still, in Marx's terms, "a class in itself." What is needed is the radicalization of the masses worldwide to challenge key aspects of the anthropocentric industrial capitalist civilization. No one knows how and when such radicalizations will occur. And if such a thing happens, how harmonious will it be among the different strata of social factors that will enable an Ecocentric Socialist revolution. We still need to develop a theory of how the vanguard of such a movement should be organized not to become an elite force, but to enable further development of the revolution. Finally, the current world political situation is characterized by inter-imperialist rivalry, as seen in the Ukraine war, which threatens humanity with World War III and nuclear annihilation. Also, with the extreme marginalization of socialist and ecological socialist, labor and green organizations, there has been no mass antiwar protest. The ecological/green movement has been coopted into the framework of capitalist electoral politics discussing how to live with these calamities in place of overcoming the system that produces them. At the same time, ecological existential crises have limited the window of opportunity for humanity to act as a single entity to resolve these crises (Nayeri March 2022). 

The future of humanity and most of life on planet Earth is at risk.

References:

Bhaskar, Roy. The Possibility of Naturalism. Second edition. 1979.

——————. "Philosophy of Social Sciences." In Twentieth Century Social Thought. Edited by William Outhwaite & Tom Bottomore, Ernest Gellner, Robert Nisbet, and Allain Touraine. 1994.

Burkett, Paul.  Marx and Nature: A Red and Green Perspective. 1999.

Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. 1962.

Chattopadhyay, Paresh. "Marx and the Progress." September 2000.

Draper, Hal. " The Principle of Self-Emancipation in Marx and Engels," 1971.

————–.  Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution: Volume II, The Politics of Social Classes. 1978.

Engels, Frederick.  Condition of the Working Class in England. 1845.

________________. The Peasant War in Germany. 1850.

________________. Socialism: Utopian and Scientific. 1880.

________________. "Speech at the Grave of Karl Marx." 1883.

Filmer, Deon. " Estimating the World at Work," background report for the World Bank, World Development Report 1995. 1995.

Foster, John Bellamy. Marx 's Ecology: Materialism and Nature. 2000.

Foster, John Bellamy, Brett Clark, and Richard York.  The Ecological Rift: Capitalism 's War on the Earth.  2010.

Graeber, David, and David Wengrow.  The Dawn of Everything: A New History of Humanity. 2021.

Green, Roy. "Rudolf Hilferding," in Marxian Economics, The New Palgrave, 1990, pp. 201-04

Guevara, Ernesto Che.  Socialism and Man in Cuba. 1965.

Haupt, George Peter Fawcett, and Eric Hobsbawm (ed.) Aspects of International Socialism: 1871-1914: Essays by George Haupt. 2010.

Harman, Chris. "The Workers of the World." International Socialism Journal. Autumn, 2002.

Lenin, V. I What Is to Be Done? Burning Questions of our Movement. 1902.

—————.  The State and Revolution: The Marxist Theory of the State and the Tasks of the Proletariat. 1917

—————.  Lenin 's Final Fight: Speeches and Writings 1922-23. 2010.

Kovel, Joel.  The Enemy of Nature: The End of Capitalism or the End of the World?  2002.

Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 1962.

Lih, Lars T. “All Power to the Soviets!' Biography of a Slogan.” The Bullet, July 2017.

Löwy, Michael.  Ecosocialism: A Radical Alternative to Capitalist Catastrophe. 2015.

Mandel, Ernest.  The Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx. 1971.

Marx, Karl.  Economic & Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844. 1844.

_________.  Theses on Feuerbach. 1845.

_________.  The German Ideology:  Critique of Modern German Philosophy According to Its Representatives Feuerbach, B. Bauer and Stirner, and of German Socialism According to Its Various Prophets. 1845-46.

_________.  A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy: Preface. 1859.

_________. " Provisional Rules of the Association, in The General Council of the International Workingmen’s Association. October 21 and 27, 1864.

_________. Letter to Wilhelm Liebknecht. February 11, 1878.

Meek, Ronald. Social Science and the Noble Savage. 1976/2010.

Mészáros, Istaván. Marx’s Theory of Alienation. 1970.

Miéville, China. October 2017.

Nayeri, Kamran. The Role of Competition in Theories of Late Capitalist Development. Ph.D. dissertation. New School for Social Research. 1991.

_____________. “Socialism and the Market: Methodological Issues in Economic Calculations Debate,” Critique, December 2004.

——————-. “Marx and Engels and Trade Unions.” Negah, 2005. In Farsi.

——————-. “Helen Yaffe’s Che Guevara: The Economics of Revolution.” Journal of History of Economic Thought, 2010.

————————-. Economics, Socialism, and Ecology: A Critical Outline, Part 2.” Philosophers for Change, October 2013.

————————. “Join the March for Climate Justice on September 21.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. August 2014

————————-.People’s Climate March Was a Huge Success; What to Do Next?” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. October 2014

————————.How to Stop the Sixth Extinction: A Critical Assessment of E. O. Wilson’s Half-Earth.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. May 14, 2017.

————————. On China Miéville’s ‘October.’” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. December 2017.

————————.Capitalism, Automation, and Socialism: Karl Marx on the Labor Process.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. June 2018.

_______________. “On Dependency School and Monopoly Capitalism Theory.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. August 2018.

————————. “The Crisis of Civilization and How to Resolve It: An Introduction to Ecocentric Socialism.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. October 2018.

————————.The Coronavirus Pandemic as the Crisis of Civilization.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. March 2020.

————————. “A Critical Theoretical Assessment of the U.S. Socialist Workers Party: Past and Present.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism. October 20, 2020.

————————-. “The Case for Ecocentric Socialism.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism, July 2021

————————-. “Humanity at Crossroads.” Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism, March 2022.

________________. Whose Planet? Essays on Ecocentric Socialism. 2023A.

________________. Toward a Theory of Uneven and Combined Late Capitalist Development. 2023B.

________________. "The Economic and Political Thoughts of Ernesto Che Guevara." Our Place in the World: A Journal of Ecosocialism, May 1, 2024. 

O’Connor, James. Natural Causes: Essays in Ecological Marxism. 1998.

Shaikh, Anwar. Capitalism, Conflict, Crises. 2016.

Shaikh, Anwar and E. Ahmet Tonak. Measuring the Wealth of Nations: The Political Economy of National Accounts. 2010.

Silverman, Bertram. Man and Socialism: The Great Debate. 1971.

Steffen, Will, et.al.Four of the Nine Planetary Boundaries Have Now Been Crossed.” Stockholm Resilience Center, January 15, 2015

Tablada, Carlos. Che Guevara: Economics and Politics in Transition to Socialism. (Spanish edition 1987; English edition. 1989)

The International Geosphere-Biosphere Program.The Great Acceleration.” 2015.

Trotsky, Leon. The Revolution Betrayed: What is the Soviet Union and Where is it Going? 1936.

___________. The Death Agony of Capitalism and the Tasks of the Fourth International: The Mobilization of the Masses around Transitional Demands to Prepare the Conquest of Power. 1938.

Yaffe, Helen. Che Guevara: The Economics of Revolution. 2009.

Zinoviev. Gregory.  The Social Roots of Opportunism. 1916.


Endnotes:

1.Engels in a footnote to the 1888 English edition and the 1890 German edition  of The Communist Manifesto wrote:  “That is, all written history. In 1847, the pre-history of society, the social organisation existing previous to recorded history, all but unknown. Since then, August von Haxthausen (1792-1866) discovered common ownership of land in Russia, Georg Ludwig von Maurer proved it to be the social foundation from which all Teutonic races started in history, and, by and by, village communities were found to be, or to have been, the primitive form of society everywhere from India to Ireland. The inner organization of this primitive communistic society was laid bare, in its typical form, by Lewis Henry Morgan's (1818-1881) crowning discovery of the true nature of the gens and its relation to the tribe. With the dissolution of the primeval communities, society begins to be differentiated into separate and finally antagonistic classes. I have attempted to retrace this dissolution in The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, second edition, Stuttgart, 1886.”

2. It must be noted that with the passage of time, Marx’s focus on human emancipation was replaced with emancipation of the proletariat in the socialist movement which because more or less the movement to improve the lot of the working people by substituting various other social forces and in the best case to bring proletariat to power. Marx’s focus on socialism as the society that does away with alienation has been quietly forgotten. 

3. "It is true that Mehring reprinted some of Marx's early published works in 1902 ... but the more important writings remained unknown. And anyway, by that time all the first generation of Marxist commentators and followers - including Kautsky, Plekhanov, Bernstein and Labriola [63] - had already formed their ideas. Therefore, the Marxism of the Second International was formed almost in total neglect of the difficult and complex process that Marx had gone through in the years 1843-1845 when he formulated historical materialism for the first time.”  From Lucio Coletti’s “Introduction” to "Karl Marx, Early Writings," Penguin Books, 1972.

4. By replacing Marx's labor theory of value with the neoclassical theory of price, Baran and Sweezy developed a coherent theory of capitalist monopoly: "[T]he general theory of price for an economy dominated by such [oligopolistic] firms is the traditional monopoly price theory of classical and neoclassical economics." (Baran and Sweezy, 1966, p. 59). However, they were mistaken in their understanding of Marx’s theory of competition, hence his labor theory of value. For a full discussion and empirical evidence of the relevance of Marx's law of value to the US economy, see Anwar Sheikh, 2016.

5. Foster and Burkett (2017, p. 79)  inspired by Maurice Mandelbaum, define the materialism of the 19th century "of which Marx and Engels were among the greatest representatives," as: "There is an independent world; The human mind does not exist as an entity distinct from the human body; And there is no God (or any other non-human being) whose mode of existence is not like that of material entities.”  It is clear that this view of materialism leave aside nature and focus on humanity and society to the exclusion of the animated nature.

No comments:

Post a Comment